Is econometrics the pinnacle of economics? Read my lips — It isn’t!

5 Dec, 2013 at 14:53 | Posted in Statistics & Econometrics | 10 Comments

LierAs social scientists – and economists – we have to confront the all-important question of how to handle uncertainty and randomness. Should we define randomness with probability? If we do, we have to accept that to speak of randomness we also have to presuppose the existence of nomological probability machines, since probabilities cannot be spoken of – and actually, to be strict, do not at all exist – without specifying such system-contexts. Accepting Haavelmo’s domain of probability theory and sample space of infinite populations – just as Fisher’s “hypothetical infinite population, of which the actual data are regarded as constituting a random sample”, von Mises’s “collective” or Gibbs’s ”ensemble” – also implies that judgments are made on the basis of observations that are actually never made!

Infinitely repeated trials or samplings never take place in the real world. So that cannot be a sound inductive basis for a science with aspirations of explaining real-world socio-economic processes, structures or events. It’s not tenable.

As David Salsburg once noted – in his lovely The Lady Tasting Tea – on probability theory:

[W]e assume there is an abstract space of elementary things called ‘events’ … If a measure on the abstract space of events fulfills certain axioms, then it is a probability. To use probability in real life, we have to identify this space of events and do so with sufficient specificity to allow us to actually calculate probability measurements on that space … Unless we can identify [this] abstract space, the probability statements that emerge from statistical analyses will have many different and sometimes contrary meanings.

Just as e. g. John Maynard Keynes and Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen, Salsburg is very critical of the way social scientists – including economists and econometricians – uncritically and without arguments have come to simply assume that one can apply probability distributions from statistical theory on their own area of research:

Probability is a measure of sets in an abstract space of events. All the mathematical properties of probability can be derived from this definition. When we wish to apply probability to real life, we need to identify that abstract space of events for the particular problem at hand … It is not well established when statistical methods are used for observational studies … If we cannot identify the space of events that generate the probabilities being calculated, then one model is no more valid than another … As statistical models are used more and more for observational studies to assist in social decisions by government and advocacy groups, this fundamental failure to be able to derive probabilities without ambiguity will cast doubt on the usefulness of these methods.

This importantly also means that if you cannot show that data satisfies all the conditions of the probabilistic nomological machine – including e. g. the distribution of the deviations corresponding to a normal curve – then the statistical inferences used, lack sound foundations.

In his great book Statistical Models and Causal Inference: A Dialogue with the Social Sciences David Freedman also touched on these fundamental problems, arising when you try to apply statistical models outside overly simple nomological machines like coin tossing and roulette wheels (emphasis added):

Of course, statistical models are applied not only to coin tossing but also to more complex systems. For example, “regression models” are widely used in the social sciences, as indicated below; such applications raise serious epistemological questions  …

A case study would take us too far afield, but a stylized example – regression analysis used to demonstrate sex discrimination in salaries – may give the idea. We use a regression model to predict salaries (dollars per year) of employees in a firm from: education (years of schooling completed), experience (years with the firm), and the dummy variable “man,” which takes the value 1 for men and 0 for women. Employees are indexed by the subscript i; for example, salaryi; is the salary of the ith employee. The equation is

(3) salaryi = a + b*educationi + c*experiencei + d*mani + εi.

Equation (3) is a statistical model for the data, with unknown parameters a, b, c, d; here, a is the “intercept” and the others are “regression coefficients”; εi is an unobservable error term. … In other words, an employee’s salary is determined as if by computing

(4) a + b*education + c*experience + d*man,

then adding an error drawn at random from a box of tickets. The display (4) is the expected value for salary given the explanatory variables (education, experience, man); the error term in (3) represents deviations from the expected.

The parameters in (3) are estimated from the data using least squares. If the estimated coefficient d for the dummy variable turns out to be positive and “statistically significant” (by a “t-test”), that would be taken as evidence of disparate impact: men earn more than women, even after adjusting for differences in background factors that might affect productivity. Education and experience are entered into equation (3) as “statistical controls,” precisely in order to claim that adjustment has been made for differences in backgrounds …

The story about the error term – that the ε’s are independent and identically distributed from person to person in the data set – turns out to be critical for computing statistical significance. Discrimination cannot be proved by regression modeling unless statistical significance can be established, and statistical significance cannot be established unless conventional presuppositions are made about unobservable error terms.

Lurking behind the typical regression model will be found a host of such assumptions; without them, legitimate inferences cannot be drawn from the model. There are statistical procedures for testing some of these assumptions. However, the tests often lack the power to detect substantial failures. Furthermore, model testing may become circular; breakdowns in assumptions are detected, and the model is redefined to accommodate. In short, hiding the problems can become a major goal of model building.

Using models to make predictions of the future, or the results of interventions, would be a valuable corrective. Testing the model on a variety of data sets – rather than fitting refinements over and over again to the same data set – might be a good second-best … Built into the equation is a model for non-discriminatory behavior: the coefficient d vanishes. If the company discriminates, that part of the model cannot be validated at all.

Regression models like (3) are widely used by social scientists to make causal inferences; such models are now almost a routine way of demonstrating counterfactuals. However, the “demonstrations” generally turn out to depend on a series of untested, even unarticulated, technical assumptions. Under the circumstances, reliance on model outputs may be quite unjustified. Making the ideas of validation somewhat more precise is a serious problem in the philosophy of science. That models should correspond to reality is, after all, a useful but not totally straightforward idea – with some history to it. Developing appropriate models is a serious problem in statistics; testing the connection to the phenomena is even more serious …

In our days, serious arguments have been made from data. Beautiful, delicate theorems have been proved, although the connection with data analysis often remains to be established. And an enormous amount of fiction has been produced, masquerading as rigorous science.

And as if this wasn’t enough, one could also seriously wonder what kind of “populations” these statistical and econometric models ultimately are based on. Why should we as social scientists – and not as pure mathematicians working with formal-axiomatic systems without the urge to confront our models with real target systems – unquestioningly accept Haavelmo’s “infinite population”, Fisher’s “hypothetical infinite population”, von Mises’s “collective” or Gibbs’s ”ensemble”?

Of course one could treat our observational or experimental data as random samples from real populations. I have no problem with that. But probabilistic econometrics does not content itself with that kind of populations. Instead it creates imaginary populations of “parallel universes” and assume that our data are random samples from that kind of populations.

But this is actually nothing else but hand-waving! And it is inadequate for real science. As David Freedman writes in Statistical Models and Causal Inference (emphasis added):

With this approach, the investigator does not explicitly define a population that could in principle be studied, with unlimited resources of time and money. The investigator merely assumes that such a population exists in some ill-defined sense. And there is a further assumption, that the data set being analyzed can be treated as if it were based on a random sample from the assumed population. These are convenient fictions … Nevertheless, reliance on imaginary populations is widespread. Indeed regression models are commonly used to analyze convenience samples … The rhetoric of imaginary populations is seductive because it seems to free the investigator from the necessity of understanding how data were generated.

10 Comments

  1. How many doctorate degrees that need to be revoked are we talking about here? Because for me this is what it boils down to. It is those very same people who assumed an imaginary distribution from limited observations that go in a classroom and continue doing the same thing corrupting student minds.

  2. the other piece was the following, deleted by accident: “The Relative/Absolute Nature of Knowledge and Economic Analysis” by Tony Lawson

  3. And “Uncertainty, Conventional Behavior, and Economic Sociology” by Jörg Bibow, Paul Lewis and Jochen Runde

  4. One of my favorite pieces related to this issue is by Tony Lawson: “The Relative/Absolute Nature of Knowledge and Economic Analysis”.

    • Bibow, Runde, Lawson — I couldn’t have made better choices myself. Must-reads!

      • If you are every looking for research assistant, I am first in line! 🙂

        Med vänlig hälsning och verkligen,
        David

        • I’ll keep it in mind for the future!
          And I have to say I’m really impressed by your Swedish. But I guess you may have someone near at hand to help you a little … 🙂

          Bästa Malmöhälsningar från “Backarna”!

          • Well, my beautiful wife is an excellent teacher! I can send you my cv, if you are interested. All my best, David

  5. From a mathematical point of view, it is important to realise that the existence of ‘objective’ probabilities is generally doubtful, while in all but the simplest and most certain situations the use of subjective probabilities is risky.

    For example, dynamic stochastic systems can have multiple phases, corresponding to different probability distributions. Such systems can transit between phases, otherwise they resemble conventional equilibria in the short run.

    It seemed to me that from at least 2005 the global economy had some very different phases and – contra mainstream economics – there seemed no reason why the then current phase should endure indefinitely. The other phases formed virtual economic systems, which we might have done well to pay more attention to, even if they did seem like mythical ‘parallel universes’.

    Most probability theory and statistics, such as the law of large numbers, tends to assume an equilibrium. While the (apparent) equilibrium behaviour is important, we might do well to look more broadly, from time to time.


Sorry, the comment form is closed at this time.

Blog at WordPress.com.
Entries and Comments feeds.