Chicago economics — the triumph of empty formalism
28 Feb, 2021 at 15:50 | Posted in Economics | Comments Off on Chicago economics — the triumph of empty formalism
Vielleicht ist diese Grundperspektive der radikalen Trennung von Form und Gehalt hilfreich, einige zunächst überaus paradoxe Äußerungen von Lucas etwas zu erhellen. Erinnert man sich der Forderungen von Lucas, die Makroökonomik zwingend auf Basis der klassischen Postulate, die Lucas und Sargent (1978) als (a) „Markträumung“ und (b) „Eigennutz“ umrissen hatten, zu errichten, so erstaunt man doch angesichts Passagen wie der folgenden:
“In recent years, the meaning of the term “equilibrium” has undergone such dramatic development that a theorist of the 1930s would not recognize it. It is now routine to describe an economy following a multivariate stochastic process as being “in equilibrium,” by which is meant nothing more than that at each point in time, postulates (a) and (b) above are satisfied. This development, which stemmed mainly from work by K. J. Arrow […] and G. Debreu […], implies that simply to look at any economic time series and conclude that it is a “disequilibrium phenomenon” is a meaningless observation. Indeed, a more likely conjecture […] is that the general hypothesis that a collection of time series describes an economy in competitive equilibrium is without con tent.” (Lucas und Sargent 1978: 58-9)”
Zunächst ist man erstaunt, weil die Argumentation nicht nur kontraintuitiv, sondern geradezu widersinnig erscheint: Wie passt das zusammen, dass Lucas und Sargent einerseits einfordern, jegliche Makrotheorie habe von den Prinzipien „Markträumung bzw. Gleichgewicht“ und „Eigennutz bzw. Optimierung“ auszugehen, wenn sie direkt anschließend konstatieren, dass solche Aussagen inhaltsleer und ohne Bedeutung sind? Die hier gelieferte Verteidigung der Gleichgewichtsannahme „geräumter Märkte“ hat demnach für Lucas gar nichts mit jener alltäglichen Bedeutung zu tun, wonach der Markt für Äpfel geräumt ist, wenn wie beobachten können, dass alle angebotenen Äpfel auch gekauft werden. Markträumung als Konzept ist somit kein Ereignis, dass mit der Realität korrespondiert, sondern ein Modellbaukonzept, mit dem Modellstrukturen erzeugt werden kön nen, die Zeitreihen nachbilden können. Die Begriffe „Markträumung“ und „Eigennutz“ haben eben in diesem Sinne keine empirische, oder reale Bedeutung, wie Lucas und Sargent klar herausstellen, sie dienen nur zur Erzeugung der formalen Struktur des Modells, sie sind jedoch losgelöst von ihrer (anschaulichen) Bedeutung oder Interpretation.
In case your German isn’t to rusty, Cruccolini’s dissertation on the development of modern macroeconomics is highly recommended reading.
Some of us have for years been urging economists to pay attention to the ontological foundations of their assumptions and models. Sad to say, economists have not hearkened the appeal — and so modern economics has become increasingly irrelevant to the understanding of the real world.
Within mainstream economics internal validity is still everything and external validity nothing. Why anyone should be interested in that kind of theories and models is beyond imagination. As long as mainstream economists do not come up with any export-licenses for their theories and models to the real world in which we live, they really should not be surprised if people say that this is not science.
Studying mathematics and logics is interesting and fun. It sharpens the mind. In pure mathematics and logics we do not have to worry about external validity. But — economics is not pure mathematics or logics. It’s about society. The real world. Forgetting that, economics is in dire straits.
The scientific method arose as a rejection of the axiomatic method used by the Greeks for scientific methodology. It was this rejection of axiomatics and logical certainty in favour of empirical and observational approach which led to dramatic progress in science. However, this did involve giving up the certainties of mathematical argumentation and learning to live with the uncertainties of induction. Economists need to do the same — abandon current methodology borrowed from science and develop a new methodology suited for the study of human beings and societies.
Logistic regression (student stuff)
27 Feb, 2021 at 16:02 | Posted in Statistics & Econometrics | Comments Off on Logistic regression (student stuff).
In the video below (in Swedish) yours truly shows how to perform a logit regression using Gretl.
Avec le temps
26 Feb, 2021 at 17:04 | Posted in Varia | Comments Off on Avec le temps.
Quel chef d’oeuvre! Cette tellement triste, belle et émouvante chanson, touche le plus profond de mon âme.
Dis, quand reviendras-tu?
26 Feb, 2021 at 13:49 | Posted in Varia | Comments Off on Dis, quand reviendras-tu?.
Models and laws in economics
25 Feb, 2021 at 23:51 | Posted in Economics | Comments Off on Models and laws in economics
Great lecture on how to do — and not to do — economics, delivered by Robert Skidelsky.
Fighting neoliberalism with Keynes and Minsky
25 Feb, 2021 at 18:36 | Posted in Economics | Comments Off on Fighting neoliberalism with Keynes and MinskyCovid-19 — la situation en Suède
24 Feb, 2021 at 21:56 | Posted in Politics & Society | Comments Off on Covid-19 — la situation en Suède.
Why economists understand less today than they did a century ago
24 Feb, 2021 at 18:14 | Posted in Economics | 1 CommentThe leap of generalization
24 Feb, 2021 at 16:45 | Posted in Statistics & Econometrics | Comments Off on The leap of generalizationStatistician Andrew Gelman has an interesting blogpost up on what inference in science really means:
I like Don Rubin’s take on this, which is that if you want to go from association to causation, state very clearly what the assumptions are for this step to work. The clear statement of these assumptions can be helpful in moving forward …
Another way to say this is that all inference is about generalizing from sample to population, to predicting the outcomes of hypothetical interventions on new cases. You can’t escape the leap of generalization. Even a perfectly clean randomized experiment is typically of interest only to the extent that it generalizes to new people not included in the original study.
I agree — but that’s also why we so often fail (even when having the best intentions) when it comes to making generalizations in social sciences.
What strikes me again and again when taking part of the results of randomized experiments is that they really are very similar to theoretical models. They all have the same basic problem — they are built on rather artificial conditions and have difficulties with the ‘trade-off’ between internal and external validity. The more artificial conditions, the more internal validity, but also less external validity. The more we rig experiments/models to avoid the ‘confounding factors,’ the less the conditions are reminiscent of the real ‘target system.’ The nodal issue is basically about how scientists using different isolation strategies in different ‘nomological machines’ attempt to learn about causal relationships. I doubt the generalizability of the (randomized or not) experiment strategy because the probability is high that causal mechanisms are different in different contexts and that lack of homogeneity/stability/invariance don’t give us warranted export licenses to the ‘real’ societies.
Evidence-based theories and policies are highly valued nowadays. Randomization is supposed to best control for bias from unknown confounders. The received opinion — including Rubin and Gelman — is that evidence based on randomized experiments therefore is the best.
More and more economists have also lately come to advocate randomization as the principal method for ensuring being able to make valid causal inferences. Especially when it comes to questions of causality, randomization is nowadays considered some kind of “gold standard”. Everything has to be evidence-based, and the evidence has to come from randomized experiments.
But just as econometrics, randomization is basically a deductive method. Given the assumptions (such as manipulability, transitivity, Reichenbach probability principles, separability, additivity, linearity, etc., etc.) these methods deliver deductive inferences. The problem, of course, is that we will never completely know when the assumptions are right. [And although randomization may contribute to controlling for confounding, it does not guarantee it, since genuine ramdomness presupposes infinite experimentation and we know all real experimentation is finite. And even if randomization may help to establish average causal effects, it says nothing of individual effects unless homogeneity is added to the list of assumptions.] Real target systems are seldom epistemically isomorphic to our axiomatic-deductive models/systems, and even if they were, we still have to argue for the external validity of the conclusions reached from within these epistemically convenient models/systems. Causal evidence generated by randomization procedures may be valid in ‘closed’ models, but what we usually are interested in, is causal evidence in the real target system we happen to live in.
Many advocates of randomization want to have deductively automated answers to fundamental causal questions. But to apply ‘thin’ methods we have to have ‘thick’ background knowledge of what’s going on in the real world, and not in (ideally controlled) experiments. Conclusions can only be as certain as their premises — and that also goes for methods based on randomized experiments.
So yours truly agrees with Gelman that “all inference is about generalizing from sample to population.” But I don’t think randomized experiments — ideal or not — take us very far on that road. Randomized experiments in social sciences are far from being the ‘gold standard’ they so often are depicted as.
Frank Hahn on the value of equilibrium economics
22 Feb, 2021 at 10:16 | Posted in Economics | Comments Off on Frank Hahn on the value of equilibrium economics
It cannot be denied that there is something scandalous in the spectacle of so many people refining the analyses of economic states which they give no reason to suppose will ever, or have ever, come about. It probably is also dangerous. Equilibrium economics … is easily convertible into an apologia for existing economic arrangements and it is frequently so converted.
Keynes on the methodology of econometrics
21 Feb, 2021 at 20:39 | Posted in Statistics & Econometrics | Comments Off on Keynes on the methodology of econometrics
There is first of all the central question of methodology — the logic of applying the method of multiple correlation to unanalysed economic material, which we know to be non-homogeneous through time. If we are dealing with the action of numerically measurable, independent forces, adequately analysed so that we were dealing with independent atomic factors and between them completely comprehensive, acting with fluctuating relative strength on material constant and homogeneous through time, we might be able to use the method of multiple correlation with some confidence for disentangling the laws of their action … In fact we know that every one of these conditions is far from being satisfied by the economic material under investigation.
Letter from John Maynard Keynes to Royall Tyler (1938)
On the irrelevance of mainstream economics
20 Feb, 2021 at 12:06 | Posted in Economics | Comments Off on On the irrelevance of mainstream economicsThere is something about the way mainstream economists construct their models nowadays that obviously doesn’t sit right.
One might have hoped that humbled by the manifest failure of its theoretical pretences during the latest economic-financial crises, the one-sided, almost religious, insistence on axiomatic-deductivist modelling as the only scientific activity worthy of pursuing in economics would give way to methodological pluralism based on ontological considerations rather than formalistic tractability. But — empirical evidence still only plays a minor role in mainstream economic theory, where models largely function as a substitute for empirical evidence.
The dominant ideology in the economics academy, I am maintaining, is precisely the extraordinarily wide-spread and long-lasting belief that mathematical modelling is somehow neutral at the level of content or form, but an essential method for science, underpinning any proper or serious economics …
The scandal of modern economics is not that it gets so many things wrong, but that it is so largely irrelevant. However in being irrelevant … the mainstream modelling orientation cannot but serve to deflect criticism from the nature of status quo at the level of the economy and thereby work to sustain it … In truth, few people take any mainstream analysis seriously, except in economics faculties’ promotion exercises.
If macroeconomic models — no matter of what ilk — build on microfoundational assumptions of representative actors, rational expectations, market clearing, and equilibrium, and we know that real people and markets cannot be expected to obey these assumptions, the warrants for supposing that conclusions or hypotheses of causally relevant mechanisms or regularities can be bridged, are obviously non-justifiable. Incompatibility between actual behaviour and the behaviour in macroeconomic models building on representative actors and rational expectations microfoundations is not a symptom of ‘irrationality.’ It rather shows the futility of trying to represent real-world target systems with models flagrantly at odds with reality.
A gadget is just a gadget – and no matter how many brilliantly silly mathematical models you come up with, they do not help us working with the fundamental issues of modern economies. The mainstream economics project is — mostly because of its irrelevance — seriously harmful to most people, but also seriously harmless for those who benefit from the present status quo of our societies.
Ekonomi – vetenskap eller gissningslek?
19 Feb, 2021 at 11:15 | Posted in Economics | Comments Off on Ekonomi – vetenskap eller gissningslek? Är nationalekonomi vetenskapligt baserad kunskap? Kan man förutspå hur enskilda individer eller hela samhällen kommer att agera ekonomiskt? Till exempel om miljonbonusar gör toppchefer mer lojala mot de företag som anställt dom? Kan ekonomiska analytiker verkligen se in i framtiden och förutspå kommande kriser? Eller handlar ekonomernas prognoser mer om en kvalificerad gissningslek?
Yours truly, Tore Ellingsen, och Daniel Waldenström ger sina svar i det här avsnittet av P1:s Vetandets värld.
Economics — where does it lead us?
19 Feb, 2021 at 09:51 | Posted in Economics | 2 Comments
The issue of interpreting economic theory is, in my opinion, the most serious problem now facing economic theorists. The feeling among many of us can be summarized as follows. Economic theory should deal with the real world. It is not a branch of abstract mathematics even though it utilizes mathematical tools. Since it is about the real world, people expect the theory to prove useful in achieving practical goals. But economic theory has not delivered the goods. Predictions from economic theory are not nearly as accurate as those offered by the natural sciences, and the link between economic theory and practical problems … is tenuous at best. Economic theory lacks a consensus as to its purpose and interpretation. Again and again, we find ourselves asking the question “where does it lead?”
Blog at WordPress.com.
Entries and Comments feeds.